dimanche 16 septembre 2018

Nostalgia and Alienation at the Tower Bridge

After ascending the Tower Bridge in London, viewing its in-house museum, and peering vertiginously into the River Thames through sections of glass flooring, you have the option of continuing into the bridge's engine rooms to learn more, via a display of Victorian mechanics, about the bridge's historical workings. At the end of this second section of the tour, a short documentary plays on a loop. The film features archival photos over which play voice recordings of past bridge workers describing their time working on the bridge.

The film is more moving than one might expect in what is, essentially, a museum devoted to a steam engine. The workers speak of their nervousness the first time they were left in charge of raising the bridge, their devotion to the bridge in the face of long hours, and their pride at having played a small roll in the bridge's life. One worker notes the fact that, no matter where you travel in the world, you are likely soon to see an image of the Tower Bridge in one form or another. "That's my bridge," he says.

These memoirs fly in the face of a good deal of Marxist theory. The kind of work these men, by their own accounts, devoted themselves to and take enormous personal pride in having done is, more or less, the kind of work a certain kind of 19th-century radical (both Marxist and otherwise) saw as the epitome of alienated labour. Here are men employed not for themselves but by an impersonal state, men producing neither goods for use nor even goods for trade, but rather providing a service to international trade over which they have no control. While some of the men working on the bridge are trained in specific skills, none of them did work one could call artisanal. They own neither a set of skills they can call their own nor the products of their own labour. In short, this is the kind of industrial labour that, to both Marxists and less systematic dissenters like William Morris, should have alienated the workers forced to do it.

How, then, to account for these men and their apparently heartfelt pride in their work? The condescending answer would be simple false-consciousness: These men have been so indoctrinated into state capitalism that they have learned to love their own oppression. In general terms, there is certainly something to this notion. History is not lacking for people who have defended, sometimes to the death, systems that oppose their own best interests.

That explanation, however, seems hard to apply in its full force to comfortably well-off workers in a generally liberal democracy. That is to say, these are not men denied the opportunity to learn of other possible ways of life or so impoverished that they could not have sought other jobs.

If false-consciousness doesn't fully cut it, then, there seems to me to be another, less systematised, and maybe more literary, explanation: nostalgia.

This interaction between alienation and nostalgia is maybe easiest to see in the current, crudely political case of Trumpian yearning for traditional factory jobs.

We might look at it this way: It is not immediately obvious that regimented, assembly-line jobs are a working-class utopia, and you do not need to dig very far into labour history to discover that such jobs were, in their supposed heyday, often greatly disliked; one could write a history running from the sit-down strikes in Ford plants in the 1930s through to the dens of iniquity that some GM plants were the 1980s. Yet Trump and his ideologues yearn, or at least claim to yearn, for a return to these jobs. Given the details of both the jobs in question and the history of labour organising when those jobs were dominant in the American economy, it would seem that there is less a careful theory of labour here than a knee-jerk desire for the good old days.

Surely something similar is at work in the Tower Bridge. Our smiles at these working-class recollections have as much nostalgia in them as does any Trump rally, if considerably less evil.

None of this is to deny entirely the central Marxist notion of alienation. Surely there is something to the claim that some workers are more alienated from the products of their labour than are others. However, it seems equally likely that the lived experience of that alienation involves are a fair amount of nostalgia for the conditions of the generation past. And if it seems unlikely that one could ever be nostalgic for the working conditions of the modern call centre or fast fashion sweatshop, we need only turn to Upton Sinclair's thoughts about the coal mining jobs some commentators today so desperately want back.

If alienation is 50% nostalgia, the clear problem is how far back that nostalgia runs. If I am nostalgic for the work my grandfather did (an electrician in the public service, as it happens), and he was nostalgic for the work his grandfather did, is there some end point to the regress, some moment when labour was actually experienced as non-alienating in its own moment? Or is it turtles all the way down?

mardi 26 juin 2018

The Great War and Modern Memory: A Partial Defence of the 5-Paragraph Essay


The 5-paragraph essay has a terrible reputation. It is often seen by writing instructors as a simplistic formula that teaches students to prioritise form over content or, worse, simply to avoid ideas that are too complex to be squeezed into its structure. At its very worst this avoidance becomes for students a habit of mind; good ideas become those which can be explicated in a single-sentence thesis, framed as one side of a two-sided debate, and defended with three "points," each supported by one or two pieces of direct textual evidence. Any idea that does not fit this structure is discarded before it is even considered. This critical view of the 5-paragraph essay is correct. The 5-paragraph essay is, in its dominant usage, a terrible formula.

And yet, it seems to me, there is some scapegoating going on here. Not everything bad about sophomoric writing can be blamed on an essay structure. Conversely (and maybe this is the more debatable point), plenty of good writing is possible within that structure. The key is the scope of the argument.

Consider Paul Fussell's classic work of cultural history The Great War and Modern Memory, originally published in 1975. In many ways, Fussell's book follows the book-length version of the 5-paragraph essay: It has an introduction framing the argument, followed by a number of chapters (the professional academic's body paragraphs) supporting the argument with different sub-claims and evidence, and then a conclusion. Fussell has more chapters than does the 5-paragraph essay have paragraphs, so his is technically a kind of 9-paragraph essay. But the basic structure remains the same.

Fussell's book, though, is extraordinarily good, not only brilliant in its analysis but a page-turner in its content, at turns shocking, amusing, and fascinating. The book achieves this level of excellence, I am arguing, not despite its conservative structure, but because of it.

Fussell's thesis is that World War 1 was narrated by its participants and remembered by the wider culture through the lens of irony, in Northrop Frye's sense of that word. Each chapter takes a different broad topic and explores it, providing evidence and analysis of the ways irony shapes our understanding of the war.

The book should suffer from obvious methodological problems. It does not propose any specific method in its approach either to historical documents or to more literary texts. It is very vague in what it sees as the relationship between writers and the underlying historical facts that shape their narratives, let alone more thorny questions of the relationships between ideologies and individual consciousnesses. It does not define its scope by a particular archive; instead it ranges widely across poems, maps, military orders, soldiers' folklore, architecture, and diaries, amongst many other forms of texts. In short, it should be kind of a mess.

What holds the book together, then, is exactly its thesis-driven structure. With an argument in place for each chapter, Fussell is free to range widely, grabbing what evidence he needs from wherever he can find it, and bringing to bear whatever methods of analysis he needs to make his case. That is to say, what makes the book work is its traditional structure: Thesis, followed by evidence, followed by analysis. The rhythms of that structure allow the content to range widely, to remarkable effect.

But if the structure is so traditional, what saves the book from being the pedantic drivel opponents of the 5-paragraph essay detest? The saving grace is the nature of the theses that drive each chapter: they are invariably broad and loose, leaving space for exploration far beyond the simple proving of a legalistic case.

Take the opening paragraph of the chapter "The Troglodyte World": "The idea of 'The Trenches' has been assimilated so successfully by metaphor and myth...that it is not easy now to recover a feeling for the actualities. Entrenched, in an expression like entrenched power, has been a dead metaphor so long that we must bestir ourselves to recover its literal sense. It is time to take a tour" (39). The argument here is clear: Insufficient attention has been paid in the literature on the war to the origin of this metaphor, and this critic is going to right that wrong. The invitation, however, is not to hear the author prove the case but, rather, to take "a tour" of some of the implications of this observation.There is argument here, but also exploration and observation.

This, it seems to me, is a model of how the thesis-driven essay (if not just the 5-paragraph one) might be resuscitated in literature classes. It is not that the structure of the argumentative paper needs to be discarded, but rather that the arguments in such a paper need to be bigger, more expansive, and more generous. There needs to be room in the structure for more than just proving your own case and refuting your enemy's.

Elsewhere in the book, Fussell addresses directly this structural concern that runs throughout the text. In the chapter "Adversary Proceedings," he criticises the tendency to collapse ideas too quickly into a simplistic frame: "As it grows politically conscious, literary discourse naturally takes on the theoretical characteristics of postwar political adversary proceedings. And that is fatal for it" (118). That is to say, literary texts that simply pick a fight with an enemy are dull if not actively deadening of their readers.

One might say the same about literary criticism. The fear of the 5-paragraph essay is grounded in a fear of generally dull and often actively simplifying, stultifying argument. The structure, so the argument goes, requires students to be pedants and bores. But we might, I am suggesting, avoid this trap without discarding entirely the standard structure of argumentative academic writing. The key, at least in the context of writing about literary and cultural ideas, might be to make arguments that are not opening briefs in adversarial proceedings, but invitations to a tour.